My good friend and colleague, Prof Jose Nandhikkara CMI of Bangalore, has kindly asked me to write an article for his excellent Dharmaram Journal on Wittgenstein and pedagogy. I am just nearing the final proofs but thought I would append some 'edited highlights' (as is usual on this site) for your amusement. It also ended up as a reflection on 20 years of teaching Wittgenstein... quite a thought!
Best wishes as always.
Peter
1.
Introduction: ‘Showing the fly the way out of the fly-bottle’
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889 – 1951) famously
characterised the aim of his philosophy as showing ‘the fly the way out of the
fly-bottle’.[1]
Much ink has been spilt as to what exactly he meant by this phrase and, indeed,
the major thrust of his philosophy tout
court (as we shall see shortly). In this article I shall present one
interpretation of the phrase. My argument will be that by working on the
gossamer-light interface between what can and cannot be said, Wittgenstein’s
philosophy gently coaxes each reader from the ensnaring prison of the
discursive intellect to a wider, non-discursive, Blick or view on existence. In so doing the philosopher, rather
like the therapist, cannot confine herself simply to words but must work on the
subtle choreography between saying and showing.
Recent
commentators such as Alain Badiou have gone so far as to suggest that
Wittgenstein is better considered as an ‘anti-philosopher’ who attacks the very
roots of Western philosophy itself. Beginning, therefore, with a brief review
of some of the problems of Wittgensteinian interpretation that have arisen in
the half century since his death in 1951, I shall then turn my attention to two
ways in which the Austrian encourages his readers to ‘work on themselves’, that
is, through the development of the Übersichtliche Blick
and a discourse that moves from thinking to seeing to acting. I shall conclude
that although some of Wittgenstein’s unorthodox methods may trouble or disturb
his readers, his ultimate aim stays deeply wedded to the ancient
quest to root philosophy in wonderment. In this respect, I will argue, we can
see his philosophy as much as therapy as pedagogy – a true working on the soul.
2. Reading Wittgenstein: Theory and Therapy
Surveying the reactions to Wittgenstein’s work
nearly fifty years after his death, Rorty in his essay “Keeping Philosophy Pure”
summed up the position thus:
Academic philosophy in our
day stands to Wittgenstein as intellectual life in Germany in the first decades
of the last century stood to Kant. Kant had changed everything, but no one was
sure just what Kant had said – no one was sure what in Kant to take seriously
and what to put aside.[2]
In this essay, Rorty
suggests that Wittgenstein’s writings throw down a gauntlet to all who read
them, especially professional philosophers. The challenge to enter the
‘transcendental standpoint’ of the Tractatus
and the further challenge of the ‘twice born’ to resist this temptation and the
challenge to both of the ‘pure of heart’ expounded in the Philosophical Investigations that transcends the need to ‘explain,
justify and expound’. In tracing this distinction, which Hutto calls the
‘theoretical and the therapeutic’,[3]
Rorty emphasises the importance of the Tractatus
for those who have expounded Wittgenstein from the former point and the
importance of the Investigations for
those of the latter disposition. This distinction between the emphases of the
work of the ‘earlier’ and ‘later’ Wittgenstein, and this possible distinction
between a theoretical and an anti-theoretical approach to his writings, has
been a constant since the voluminous Wittgensteinian secondary literature began
to swell. As Pears puts it, in these later works “he is moving away from
theorizing and towards plain description of the phenomenon of language.”[4]
Consequently, amongst the
Wittgensteinian secondary literature we see a split between those commentators
who see the work of the later Wittgenstein as continuing the work of the
earlier Wittgenstein and those who see a new anti-theoretical shift in the post-Tractatus works. To add to the confusion, a recent book, The Third Wittgenstein: The
Post-Investigations Works[5] has
argued that the parts of the Nachlass
that have appeared charting the latter period of Wittgenstein’s life, in particular
On Certainty, suggest a third interpretation of Wittgenstein
that transcends even the position developed in the Investigations.
We are thus left with four
possible ways of viewing his works in the authors of the secondary literature:
1. Those who remain with the traditional division between the ‘earlier’
and the ‘later’ Wittgenstein and see the later works, especially the Investigations, as a critique of the
earlier works, especially the Tractatus.
Representative of this trend would be Peter Hacker whose Wittgenstein: Connections and Controversies makes this point.[6]
2. The so-called ‘new Wittgensteinians’ who see a theoretical union
between the early and later Wittgenstein and reject any notion of a firm break
between the two.[7]
3. Those who regard the ‘third Wittgenstein’ of the ‘post-Investigations works’ (so-called) as
presenting a third and more radical departure from the Wittgensteinian corpus.
4. To these three interpretations, we could possibly add a fourth, a
growing body of Wittgenstein scholars who, following Wittgenstein’s own remarks
in the latter works of moving from the theoretical to the practical, or from saying to showing want to emphasise the importance of the biographical
elements of Wittgenstein’s life and use them to gain a more complete picture of
what his thought was trying to achieve. Again, a key collection of essays, Wittgenstein: Biography and Philosophy[8] has
acted as a vessel for presenting this interpretative strand. Included in this
group would be those (such as myself) who want to also emphasis the
Wittgenstein’s role as a therapist as
much as a theoretician or logician.
3.
Wittgenstein as Therapist
One of the first writers to emphasise the
‘therapeutic’ within Wittgenstein’s writing was Stanley Cavell.[9]
By the time Alice Crary’s collection The
New Wittgenstein came out in 2000 it seemed as though the notion had
influenced a whole generation of Wittgensteinian scholars. The authors
collected there, Crary suggested, shared an interpretation of Wittgenstein’s
work as a) a unified whole and b) broadly ‘therapeutic’ in nature. This
emphasises the shift in recent Wittgensteinian scholarship away from the
understanding of his work as largely theoretical
(or, in Rorty’s words, largely concerned with the reactions and concerns of
fellow ‘professional philosophers’) to an understanding which is built around
seeing his work as contributing to individual existential development.[10]
For Crary this ‘therapeutic aim’ is largely around helping us to see the
‘sources of philosophical confusion’ we hold by replacing a need for a
metaphysical view of language to a concern with the observation of the running of language as a means to solving
philosophical confusion. Thus, for Cavell, the aim of Wittgenstein’s philosophy
is to bring us back from metaphysical speculation to the everyday discourse of
‘forms of life’ (Lebensformen) where
language has its natural home. Whereas Cavell et al are primarily
concerned with the purely philosophical consequences of a reading of
Wittgenstein’s work other contemporary authors have gone further and ascribed
to Wittgenstein a therapeutic agenda that goes beyond the purely philosophical.
In this respect there has been a growing movement to connect Wittgenstein’s
writings with psychotherapeutic literature, beginning of course with his fellow
Viennese theorist, Sigmund Freud (1856 – 1939). Wittgenstein saw the value of
Freud’s work not as a pseudo-scientist but in the function of Freudian analysis
as ‘aspect-changing’:
When a dream is interpreted
we might say that it is fitted into a context in which it ceases to be
puzzling. In a sense the dreamer re-dreams his dream in surroundings such that its aspect changes…
In considering what a dream
is, it is important to consider what happens to it, the way its aspect changes
when it is brought into relation with other things remembered, for instance. (LC: 45 -46)Lectures
and Conversatons on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief. Ed C.
Barrett. Oxford: Blackwell 1989
Teaching Wittgenstein is, of course, notoriously difficult. Twenty
years ago I was assigned a class of undergraduates and told to teach them
Wittgenstein. Needless to say it was a disaster as I taught his texts
‘straight’ like any other classical philosopher such as Kant or Locke – trying
to get the class to repeat and memorise his arguments by rote (perhaps I was
unconsciously emulated Ludwig as a young man who ended up impatiently cuffing
the school-children who couldn’t follow his ice-cold but brilliant thought
processes...). Two decades later, following the interpretation I have developed
in this article, I take an entirely different approach. Having given a
preliminary lecture, not unlike the contents of this paper, I then get the
students to read the texts themselves and reflect upon them. From the ‘form of
life’ that develops in the group from the interaction of saying and showing the
true message, and transformational work, of Wittgenstein begins to happen
(much, indeed, as he taught philosophy himself in Cambridge towards the end of
his life). By using language, similes and metaphors in unusual and provocative
ways I have found that Wittgenstein brings us back to what we knew already but
were unable to express in words. In conclusion, then, it may be worth recalling
the work of Badiou whom I mentioned earlier, who termed Wittgenstein an
‘anti-philosopher’. The role of the ‘anti-philosopher’, says Badiou, has three
key elements:[11]
1.
They present ‘a
linguistic, logical, genealogical critique of the statements of philosophy...
an unraveling of the pretensions of philosophy to constitute itself a theory’.
2.
They see that philosophy
is ‘an act, of which fabulations about ‘truth’ are clothing, the propaganda,
the lies.’ (cf. T 4.112 ‘Philosophy is not a body of doctrine but an activity’).
3.
They realise that the
philosophical act “must install an active non-thought beyond all meaningful
propositions, beyond all thought, which also means beyond all science... The
antiphilosophical act consists in letting what there is show itself, insofar as
‘what there is’ is precisely that which no true proposition can say.”[12]
Badiou’s ‘anti-method’ is then, I conclude, the
spirit with which we should approach Wittgenstein’s works as a guide to
pedagogy – an approach that through the use of Übersichtliche Darstellung and astonishment will
stimulate the move from thinking to seeing to acting that will lead to the position described
finally at the end of the Tractatus:
“There are indeed things that cannot be put into words. They make themselves
manifest. They are what is mystical.”[13] But rather than ‘anti-philosopher’
I would rather conclude that Wittgenstein is the philosopher of wonderment par excellence.
[1] Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees, Oxford: Blackwell, 1958, 309.
[2]R.
Rorty, “Keeping Philosophy Pure,” in Consequences
of Pragmatism (Essays 1972 – 1980), Brighton: Harvester, 1982, 20.
[3]D.
Hutto, Wittgenstein and the End of
Philosophy: Neither Theory nor Therapy,
London: Macmillan, 2003.
[4]D. F.
Pears, The False Prison: A Study of the
Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy, Volume 1,
Oxford: Clarendon, 1988, 218.
[5]D. Moyal-Sharrock, The Third Wittgenstein: The
Post-Investigations Works., London: Ashgate, 2004.
[9]S.
Cavell, S. Must We Mean What We Say? Oxford: OUP, 1976; The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism,
Morality and Tragedy, Oxford: OUP, 1979.
[10]In this vein see, for example, J. Nandhikkara, Being Human after Wittgenstein: A
Philosophical Anthropology, Bangalore: Dharmaram Publications, 2011.
[13](T 6.522).
Hi, I am from Australia.
ReplyDeletePlease find an introduction to a unique Philosopher and Artist whose work begins where Wittgenstein inevitably got stuck. In other words he really did climb the ladder of Wittgenstein's propositions and then jumped off into the Infinite Love-Bliss-Radiance in and as which all of this is floating.
1. www.beezone.com/whiteandorangeproject/index.html multiple references on how to do philosophy and/or "theology" as a self-outgrowing and self-transcending Process
2. http://spiralledlight.wordpress.com multiple more-than-wonderful references
3. http://global.adidam.org/books/transcendental-realism an introduction to Adi Da's Divine Image Art
4. www.beezone.com/AdiDa/touch.htm radical somatic ontology
5. www.dabase.org/twoarmc.htm Love of the Two Armed Form
6. www.beezone.com/shakti/TheShaktiHerPlaywithAdiDa.html SHAKTI
7. www.dabase.org/up-6.htm The Spiritual Gospel of Saint Jesus Retold - especially section 17 on the big-time talkers who presume to rule the world
7. www.dabase.org/aletheon.htm an introduction to The Aletheon (The Truth Book)
8. www.adidaupclose.org/Literature_Theater/skalsky.html an introduction to The Orpheum Trilogy
9. www.dharmacafe.com/spiritual-heros/The-Worlds-Greatest-Unpublished-Spiritual-Book - an introduction to The Scapegoat Book (book 3 of the above trilogy)
Nhiều bạn đọc thắc mắc rằng Dùng chỉ nha khoa có tốt không? và sử dụng chỉ nha khoa có làm răng bị thưa không Quả cầu thông gió có hiệu quả không? nên lắp đặt quả cầu thông gió hay nên làm giếng trời trong nhà. Mua hè sắm đến, có rất nhiều loại trái cây để bạn giải khát, mùa của những loại vải, sầu riêng, chôm chôm. Do đó nhiều người thắc mắc Ăn nhiều chôm chôm có bị nóng không? hay Ăn nhiều vải thiếu có tốt không và Hạt dẻ Cao Bằng giá bao nhiêu?
ReplyDeleteChúng tôi chuyên nhận chuyển hàng từ nhật về việt nam và các mặt hàng ở trung quốc, chúng tôi nhận ship hàng từ trung quốc với giá cạnh tranh nhất, mang lại nhiều lợi ích cho quý khách hàng có thể tha hồ mua sắm. Nhật Bản một đất nước với nhiều địa điểm du lịch đẹp được nhiều người trong và ngoài nước biết đến, vậy khi đi nhật bản có cần visa không?